Saturday, October 19, 2013

Folk Moral Objectivism

The following paper is a response to "Folk Moral Relativism".


     The article “Folk Moral Relativism” attempts to use empirical means to show that previous studies, which concluded that most were moral objectivists, arrived at that conclusion by looking at the same culture as the respondents, and that by expanding the study to include other cultures they hoped to show that people hold a relativistic view of morality. However, while their studies may show that there is a common tendency to view that cultures hold different moral standards, the inequality of justifications of standards suggests objectivism is the folk norm.

     Before examining the article, it would be useful to understand the meaning of Moral Relativism (MR), and Moral Objectivism (MO) in this context. MR claims that the correctness of any given moral action needs to be evaluated in the context of a culture, sometimes resulting in contradictory conclusions being correct.1 MO claims that there is only one truth about morality in a similar manner as there is only one truth about empirical claims.2 If there are two competing notions of the rightness of a given action, one “is surely mistaken”.3

     Previous studies show that a majority of people hold MO to be correct, but this study set out to demonstrate that the findings were skewed by methodology, and that the truth was far more complicated.4 By pointing out that there are external facts which have a bearing on the truth of any claim, like the seasons being relative to the hemisphere, considering moral claims with reference to other cultures leads to relativistic conclusions; the more extreme the difference in cultures, the greater likelihood neither stance is viewed as wrong.5

     The first study demonstrated this by surveying students from Baruch College, New York City, on the moral correctness of two actions, killing a child based on appearance, and testing the sharpness of a knife by random stabbings. Conflicting opinions were reported of judges from wildly different cultures, two from their own culture (specifically one from their own immediate collective), one from an isolated warrior tribe, and one from an alien culture.6 The results showed that the closer to their own culture, the more likely the students would say at least one of the conflicting opinions was wrong, but that is less true as people think about different cultures.7



     To isolate the contradiction, a series of six studies was conducted using variations on the first study. The second differed only in that it was conducted at the National University of Singapore, to factor out “the idiosyncrasies of contemporary American culture.”8 It, along with the other studies, showed the same trend, a high level of confidence in the objectivity of one's cultural norms decreasing as the cultures considered diverged. Note that it focused on the judges' reactions and assumed that an answer with a low agreement was an expression of MR.

     The sixth study attempted to isolate whether people were taking the questions to mean the judge had justifications for believing as they did.9 By including non-moral facts, the researchers were able to compare the reactions “between intuitions about truth and intuitions about justifications”.10 The results showed confidence about the truth of non-moral facts, and low confidence in moral truth, contrasted with agreement that “at least one judge had 'no good reason' in the moral condition”, indicating that intuitions acknowledge cultural norms exist without any being specifically wrong, but a lower willingness to agree that all norms are equally justified.11 This seems to partially support a relativistic conclusion.

     If it is the case that people really do hold that different cultures not only have different moral norms, but that disagreements do not constitute a contradiction, we would be mistaken saying people are fundamentally moral objectivists. It may be people recognize that different cultures require sets of behaviors, and by considering different norms, people become less sure that their own culture's behaviors would be acceptable, and an apt expression of that might be the idiom, “when in Rome, do as the Romans do.” With idioms like this present in the vernacular, it would almost seem that this belief is part of a folk understanding of MR by linguistically encoding the basic notion into common phrases. Of course, the soundness of this remains firmly in the realm of empirical testing, and further studies that better isolate any psychological leanings would be necessary to confirm this conclusion.

     One key assumption in the new hypothesis is that non-moral facts have bearing on the truth of moral statement, in the same way that non-seasonal facts bear on statements about seasons. This could be called “context sensitivity”, the rightness of an action will have differing truth values based on non-moral facts.12 The argument for the new hypothesis rests completely upon this notion and the studies seems to confirm that intuitions run in a context sensitive way. If that is all that is necessary to conclude the common belief in MR, then it would appear that the hypothesis has been confirmed.

     Affirming context sensitivity is far from sufficient to affirm MR, and they are by no means equivalent. Being aware of states of affairs beyond the simple actions in question uncontroversially sheds light on the moral status of simple actions, regardless if MO or MR is true. An expert swimmer that chooses to not attempt an easy rescue of a drowning child has likely failed to meet a moral obligation, in a way that another person that is unable to swim would not have.13 This does not mean that in all situations where facts about the world play roles in the moral rightness or wrongness of rescue acts, they count as examples of MR. Like non-seasonal facts bearing on season statements, the state of affairs must be carefully examined and a large number of facts must be known before an absolute statement could be justified.

     It is completely unsurprising that people would smooth over any ambiguity of omitted facts (like what hemisphere is in question, or the behavioral norms that govern a hypothetical question) by supplying their own from the things they are most familiar, their own lives. The perceived uniformity of the same-culture conditions, which was most likely misidentified as MO, tells us nothing more than the seemingly relativistic conclusion of the new hypothesis. The study suggests that common intuitive thinking acknowledges differences exist between cultures, but that no two culture's justifications are equally supported. It is not that they feel that it is both right and wrong for the agents to perform the actions in question, but that each culture views it differently, and one of those views is better supported than the other.

     Notice, this completely leaves the question of what makes the action right or wrong, and asks a question that might be the equivalent of, “do different cultures have different beliefs, and are those beliefs as well justified as your own?” That hardly seems to be asking the right question. If we are to confirm that people are relativists, we would need to show that people think cultures are at least roughly equally justified even when they conflict.

     While the studies do show that people make a clear distinction between the truth of a moral judgment from another culture, it is unclear if that distinction counts as confirming that people are moral relativists. Instead, it is likely that they are expressing a form of context sensitivity when they are less willing to say that a judge from a different culture is wrong about moral norms, but they still believe that justifications of those norms are not equal among the cultures. Seeing that under moral relativism, it is the justified norms which make actions right or wrong, doubt of the justifications is doubt of the entire system.

Bibliography

Sarkissian, Hagop and John Park, David Tien, Jennifer Wright, Joshua Knobe. 2011. “Folk Moral Relitivism.” Mind & Language 26: 482-505

Timmons, Mark. 2013. Moral Theory: An Introduction. Plymouth: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

1 Sarkissian 2011, 482-3.
2 Sarkissian 2011, 482.
3 Sarkissian 2011, 484.
4 Sarkissian 2011, 483-5.
5 Sarkissian 2011, 485-6.
6 Sarkissian 2011, 486-8.
7 Sarkissian 2011, 489.
8 Sarkissian 2011, 489.
9 Sarkissian 2011, 497.
10 Sarkissian 2011, 498-9.
11 Sarkissian 2011, 497-500.
12 Timmons 2013, 45-6.
13 Timmons 2013, 45.

No comments:

Post a Comment