Tuesday, May 14, 2013

Cause and Effect: Humean Doubts and Kantian Answers


          To understand David Hume's criticism of the idea that we can know, in a robust and philosophical way, that there is a connection between what we call causes and effects, we must first examine how he thought our minds related to the world. Unlike the Rationalists that came before him, Hume was skeptical that reason and intuition were all that we needed for knowledge. For Hume, the first contact that we have with any object (if it exists at all) is the appearance the object has on our senses, so that the first thing that we are aware of is an impression that we have.1 Humean impressions are not simply limited to our sensual perceptions of the potential objects around us, but are also of every possible thing that we might experience, including our own internal mental processes, like emotion-states and first-order desires. Impressions are not just what we see, feel, taste, etc., but how we feel, what we want, and what motivates us. In short, impressions are the way that we first experience everything.

          From those impressions, content is directly added into the mind and forms ideas that share the same content. Hume thought this was a matter of common sense, anyone could see that while reflecting upon the painful experience of touching a burning hot object, we almost feel the same pain, but with less force than if we were actually touching something hot.2 To Hume, the impression had a strength to it that could never be matched by a mere idea, but impressions only differed from ideas in strength; the content was copied directly into the idea exactly as it was in the impression.3

          Once a series of impressions has formed a series of ideas, the imagination tends to form perceived connections between the ideas, and those connections can be evaluated according to any number of relationships they bear to each other.4 The comparative work is not a function of perception, but of imagination, and as such, it cannot involve working with impressions, but only with ideas. Of all possible relations, Hume thought that they fell into seven broad groups: resemblance, identity, space and time, quantity, quality, contrariety, and cause and effect.5 From the comparison of ideas, the imagination then sorts the ideas in a way that allows us to make sense of the impressions we receive.


          For instance, my ability to make sense of the world is dependent on my imagination's ability to run freely across all ideas that I have, compare them, and link ideas together when they meet one or more of the relationships.6 If a series of impressions of red spherical objects strikes upon my mind, the content is copied into identical but weaker ideas, and my imagination draws comparisons between each new idea and every similar idea from my memory. Each idea contains an object that is both red and round, all of the ideas might be of the same object. I have memories of similarly round objects in a wide variety of colors, they did not occur at the same time or in the same place, so I imagine that I'm viewing different, but similar objects. After surveying the relevant relations, I conclude that I am viewing a group of red balloons, a color and a term I learned sometime previous.

          In fact, I cannot have a previous idea of a balloon or the color red unless I experienced them at some time before, in the same way that I couldn't have a good idea of what a pineapple tasted like unless I tasted it.7 Of course, the impressions I received would then become an idea about the red spherical objects in the same way that the taste of an exotic fruit becomes a just idea when I taste it. However, even if my ability to reason was absolutely perfect, if I did not have previous experience to draw upon, it would be impossible for me to know anything beyond the simple impressions that struck upon my senses.8 I would not be able to look at the balloons and draw any conclusions about what would happen if I loosed them from their anchors; I could not guess that they would float upward.

          Because all ideas are copies of impressions, the cause of all ideas is direct impressions. While this might give an empirical legitimacy to the content of ideas, it does open them to questions that Hume raised about the nature of cause and effect, and that has a bearing on every potential experience that we might have. If we exclude the relationship of cause and effect, we only have a series of ideas and memories that do count as evidence of objects, but do not allow us to understand anything about the objects.9

          Hume argued that only by the relation of causality can an observer move beyond the simple idea of two objects or events that appear one after the other, e.g., the first time viewing a released balloon floating upward there is no way to conclude anything.10 Only by repeatedly releasing balloons can we conclude that by releasing the balloon (which we will call the cause)11, it will float away (which we will call the effect). By repeating this, we might believe that we have an understanding of a cause and an effect, but no matter how many balloons we release, we can never see any connection between releasing a balloon and it floating up, we only see that one event follows the other and they seem to be continually joined in our impressions, ideas, and memories.12

          Since we are unable to have a direct impression of the connection, we are unable to copy it into our ideas, or any notion of powers like the necessary and customary connections between causes and effects.13 We can only imagine and infer that a connection between them exist. If we try to use reason alone to identify an ultimate connection between causes and effects in general, reason will fail us because all we have is experiences of individual instances where it appears to us that there is a constant conjunction between objects, but we are not justified in saying that we know that it will hold for things that are outside our experience.14

Kantian Revolution
          Immanuel Kant's use of information gained by the senses is not so different from Hume's, but there are notable differences in the grounds that Kant uses to justify the inference from the senses to experience. While having direct empirical, a posterriori (reasoning from observation) experience of an object does give us the beginnings of all understanding, Kant argued that trying to derive a universal law that governed the connection we believe is needed between cause and effect from frequent associations in the experience, is a mistake that would, as Hume pointed out, leave us with no justifiable reason to think there is such a law.15 If experience is what justifies the rules that govern experience, that means that the laws we'd hope universal are merely contingent on the senses, and are not certain at all.16 To find such a universal law requires the use reason to move beyond the limitations of experience by using pure reason, i.e., objective rationality that is beyond the individual as in mathematics and the sciences, to shift the focus beyond what is possible with practical reason and sensations, even beyond the objects that present to us.17

          The major departure from Hume's position is that Kant held both the Rationalist view of the intuition and the Empiricist view of the senses as the source of knowledge. While these two seem to be at odds, Kant shows that they are both necessary for actually being able understand any possible object we might experience. His system begins with space. More specificity, it begins with any given observation of an object, when stripped of all the empirical information so that we are no longer able to consider any aspect that can give an impression of the object to us, we are left with at least one property, the space that it occupied.18 Although Hume used space as a relation the imagination uses to compare objects, there are conceptual issues with this view. Since we cannot see space, we cannot copy an impression into our ideas, and so it would not be an object of posteriori experience.

          By removing the empirical data from an object, Kant leaves only the space that the object occupied, implying that space is a non-empirical property of the object, the concept of which must come from the grounds of a priori (reasoning from previous grounds, lit. “from the former”) judgments.19 Kant does not abandon the Humean use of the concept of space as a relationship that allows us to make determinations about the outside world, but uses that very notion to begin exploring the concept of space. Before we are able to examine any spacial relations between objects and ourselves, we first have to conceive of the objects as exterior to ourselves, and all possible objects, including us, to be inside a general space.20 This is the a priori grounds from which we build the notion of separable spaces that each object occupies.

          While not an object of empirical observations, space is the basis of all experience in that we use the concept to show that two objects are unique because they appear in two different places, and space is necessary and a priori in that we can not conceive of an object without space, but we can conceive of space without objects.21 Likewise, time is an a priori foundational concept that roots our perceptions of things existing in the same moment, and gives us the successions of sensations.22 Space and time, sharing very similar intuitive properties, are forms of the way we perceive all of our sensations.23 Seeing that these a priori notions are particular to us, as humans, and may not hold for other beings, they form pure intuitions that are necessary for our a posteriori cognition to be possible.24

          When I see a group of roughly spherical red objects, it is not just that my imagination runs over all the ideas from my memories, it is that I see them at different points in space, containing a different subset of space, and all at a particular time. I can not even begin to have an impression of them without first having the a priori notions of space and time. However, the balloons do not contain the notions of space or time, they are in space and time, and that temporal-spacial reference is both outside of myself and distinct to the objects.

          Regardless of how similar my empirical perceptions of them are, I can know that they are not the same balloon repeated in my perception, because they are in different points in space at the same time. If I did not bring this a priori concept with me, there is no possible way that I could ever have anything that approaches understanding, or cognition, of the group of balloons. My a priori notion of space and time are the forms that allow me sensual experience.

          Nonetheless, I can not perceive either space or time, but must use pure reason to reach these notions, and then I must force my observations to conform to them. Kant called this a revolution, in the tradition of Copernicus, that reason should be taught by nature, but not as a student that stumbles into knowledge, but as a judge that compels nature to answer the questions necessitated by the laws pure reason proves must exist.25 Hume's method (as well as all philosophers engaged in any form of metaphysics) of trying to see the power of causality was merely groping among concepts.26

          As with space and time, in order to “see” causality, the philosopher must first show it to be a possibility. In a similar fashion to how jurists ask what is lawful and what are the facts, Kant separates the matter into transcendental deduction, which is concerned with the a priori objects in and of themselves, and the empirical deductions that are concerned with what is learned from experience.27 Space and time serve as a demonstration of the division between the transcendental and the empirical as we arrive at those concepts, which are the form of our sensibility that are necessary for the possibility of understanding, without borrowing any content from experience; any deduction of them must be transcendental.28

          In an almost direct response to Hume's problem of induction, Kant established a dichotomy of the possible ways that the objective validity of cause and effect might be dealt with, either follow Hume's course to the logical end and abandon it as a fantasy, or follow the example of the concepts of space and time, and ground causality completely on a priori understanding.29 By taking the meaning of cause and effect and producing a deductive rule that states that one object follows from another, i.e., is necessitated by another, we have an a priori rule that has a universality that can not be matched by empirical means.30 This is not to say that such a relationship does exist in reality, only that it is “legal”. It allows us to subsume any empirical observations of that form under a category, whereby we can properly cognize the event.

          If I observe that by cutting the string that held down a balloon, that it floats away, I take the series of impressions in my mind, referenced with the forms of space and time, and bring them under the transcendental categories, then I might be justified in saying that I cognized, or understood, that the immediate cause of the balloon floating upward was the cutting of the string. However, I think this hints at a potential weakness in Kant's model. While I might rightly conclude that I have understood something about the world, I have not truly grasped the full nature of what I have witnessed, in and of itself.

          Kant focuses on how it is possible for us to have cognition of objects, things in themselves, but it is conceivable that many truths about the world are beyond the limitations of human observations (or at least the current limits) and therefore beyond understanding and experience. While he does provide a possible way for us to justify empirical experience using a priori forms, we have no way of knowing if those forms actually represent anything real, or if our limited ability to reason has somehow missed a form that does exist. What I have missed is that the string did not cause the balloon to float at all, but the ultimate cause was the relationship among the lighter-than-air gas in the balloon, the atmosphere, and gravity; the cutting of the string was only an intermediate cause, but without experience with gases and gravity, I am like Hume's Adam unable to know that water will drown him.

          Still, I think Kant would reply that all that has happened was that I failed to properly cognize this situation because I was unaware of hidden causes that are fully possible in complex situations. Hidden causes and failed cognitions do not work against the a priori category of causality and dependence because they do not show that the category is impossible. We neither need to posses all possible forms, only the necessary ones for cognition to be possible, nor do the forms that pure reason has defined need to align with objects in the world for them to be potentially real. We cannot have cognition if we cannot place objects into the categories, and we cannot have justified experience if we do not have a priori means of understanding. However, much like the forms of space and time, if we are to have any experience that includes cause and effect, then we cannot be without the transcendental category.

          Hume's challenge was to how we could be rationally justified in concluding that we understood cause and effect. Kant showed that there are concepts that we cannot know except from a priori grounds, and included in those is causality. The concepts do not count as experience, but without them we can't begin to understand the objects to which they should apply. Only after we have brought the pure concepts together with the sensual impressions of an event can we possibly have experience of them. In this way, Kant provides the basis of possible experience of cause and effect, and a rational method to say that as long as we have justified means of understanding space and time that we do have justification to conclude that we can understand cause and effect, but only after we have properly subsumed a causal event into the transcendental categories can we have experience of it.

Bibliography

Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Understanding. Ed. David F. Norton and Mary J. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Hume, David. An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. Tom L. Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

1 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Understanding, ed. David F. Norton and Mary J. Norton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 1.1.1.1, pg. 7.
2 David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 2.1, pg. 96.
3 Hume, Treatise, 1.1.1.7, pg. 9.
4 Ibid., 1.1.5.1-2, pgs.14-5.
5 Ibid., 1.1.5.2-9, pg. 15.
6 Ibid., 1.1.4.1-2, pgs. 12-3.
7 Ibid., 1.1.1.9, pg. 9.
8 Hume, Enquiry, 4.1.6, pgs. 109-10.
9 Ibid., 4.1.1-4, pgs. 108-9.
10 Ibid., 7.2.26, pg. 143-4.
11 I acknowledge that the ultimate cause of the balloon floating upward is actually the density of the gas that fills the balloon being less than the atmosphere surrounding it. However, this is abstracted knowledge that is well beyond simple impressions and ideas.
12 Hume, Enquiry, 7.2.26, pg. 144.
13 Ibid., 7.1.8-15, pgs. 136-9.
14 Hume, Treatise, 1.3.6.10-11, pgs. 63-64.
15 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, ed. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood, (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2009), B1-6, 136-8.
16 Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, B5, pg. 138.
17 Ibid., Bxxv, 114.
18 Ibid., B6, pg. 138.
19 Ibid., B6, pg. 138.
20 Ibid., A23/B37, pg. 157.
21 Ibid., A23/B37-A24/B38, pg. 157-8.
22 Ibid., A31/B46, pg. 162.
23 Ibid., A42/B59, pg. 168.
24 Ibid., A42/B59-A43/B60, pg. 168.
25 Ibid., Bxiii-Bxiv, pgs. 108-9.
26 Ibid., Bxv, pg. 110.
27 Ibid., A84/B117-A85-B118, pg. 219-20.
28 Ibid., A86/B118, pg. 220.
29 Ibid., B124, pg. 223.
30 Ibid., B124, pg. 223.

No comments:

Post a Comment