Wednesday, December 18, 2013

Moral Pluralism and George's Job Search

          In this paper I will briefly lay out W. D. Ross' ethical theory, Moral Pluralism (MP), and apply it to Bernard Williams' “George the chemist” case in order to demonstrate how such a theory can resolve moral conflicts. Moral Pluralism differs from what could be called “moral monism” in that monism claims that there is a single principle that serves as an explanation of morality,1 but pluralism claims there is a collection of principles where none of them are more basic or fundamental than the rest.2 The major departure between pluralism and monism is that there is no single justification of morality, the parts of morality, or the plurality of the moral rules; the basic moral rules exist together, they cannot be derived from one another, and they are not grounded on some external principle.3
          This may seem less plausible than other theories because determinations in specific cases are usually deduced from a combination of the basic principle and the derived duties. Here, we have only a collection of duties with no principle to make use of in deciding cases. Ross did not find this problematic because he posited “prima facie” duties (PFD), a collection of basic moral duties, and what could be called “all-things-considered” duties (ATCD), the duties that are left after careful reflection on “one's duty proper … [or] one's actual duty.”4 Imagine a driver of a car on a snowy freeway. The driver has a large number of legal duties that apply to her at any given moment: the duty to keep the car in working order, to use turn signals before changing lanes, to drive safe speeds, and to keep her vehicle under her control in all weather conditions. Failing at any of one of these might count as being legally blameworthy. If an emergency vehicle should appear behind her with full lights and sirens, all the PFDs of driving are still there, but her ATCD becomes to move out of the way.

          That example may not fully illuminate the relationship between PFD and ATCD, but it is enough to understand that the thing that causes a basic duty to become a proper duty is moral judgment.5 It may not be safe for the driver to lock up her brakes while on the snowy road, or drive at speed onto the icy edge of the road, but she must use her judgment to actualize the PFD that is most relevant at the given moment. In short, she must reflect on the situation and identify the ATCD in order to take the actions associated with that duty.
          According to Ross, there are seven basic moral duties that we all share: fidelity, a duty to the truth; reparation, a duty to make amends for past wrongs; gratitude, a duty of repayment for benefits received; justice, a distribution of merit-based benefits; beneficence, a duty to benefit others; self-improvement, a duty to develop as an intellectual and moral being; and nonmaleficence, a duty to avoid harming others.6 Each PFD counts as a reason to set a particular course of action. These are not the only possible duties, but they are the most basic, and other identifiable duties are often either derived from or are combinations of these duties.7
          In order to understand how MP uses PFD to reach an ATCD, it might be helpful to think of the metaphor of the scales of Lady Justice. In any given case, each PFD is a weight placed on the scale that will count for or against doing any particular action, but in themselves, those PFDs don't make the action right or wrong.8 The duty-making feature that takes the collection of PFDs and makes an ATCD is that one action has the greatest weight of PFDs supporting that action.9 The PFDs tip the scales in favor of the morally-right duty.
          There may be some situations where one PFD is so weighty that it overrides other duties, but that does not excuse them, and may require other PFDs, like reparations for the overridden but failed duty.10 An action is required as an ATCD when the scales tip in favor of it, wrong if the scales tip in favor of forbidding that action, and optional if the scales are either empty of moral consideration, or evenly balanced.11 Actions that have no relevant PFDs are not moral decisions. When it is evenly balanced, reason alone is not sufficient to decide the matter, and something like preference under discretion is available to the agent. Given the wide applicability of the PFDs, there may be few non-trivial situations where there would be no morally relevant details to consider. Even my car example is loaded with moral considerations.
          Where this gets complex is in deciding the moral weight to give to each PFD, seeing that there is no underlying principle that directs which is most important. The first step in the decision process is to recognize that PFDs are not robust duties that dictate the strict rightness/wrongness of an action, but are a “nonlexical pluralism”, a collection of variably weighted principles that convey rightness/wrongness, but not “exceptionless” absolutes.12 To make decisions under these conditions requires that we exercise a form of moral judgment, similar to that of aesthetic judgments, where the precise nature of the decision process is dependent on the features the observer identifies as having important bearing on the ATCD.13 Like judging a work of art, the more complex a situation, the more difficult judgments become.
          To illustrate this, one need only apply the theory to a complex case, like that of George the chemist. George has a Ph.D. in Chemistry, but it is difficult to find work in that field and his failing health prevents alternative lines of work. His family is financially supported by his wife, while he attempts to look after the children—a task made burdensome by his health. He believes this situation is damaging to his family, especially the well-being of his children. A more influential chemist offers to get him work with a company that conducts research on Chemical and Biological Warfare (CBW). George opposes this because he is against CBW, but the job offer was, in part, a pretext to stop a competitor, who has no such reservations, from getting the position. George's wife, whose opinion he values, has no qualms about that type of work.14
          To apply Ross' theory to the “George” case, one must consider which of the PFDs apply to his situation. His feelings toward CBW could have an impact on the PFD of fidelity. He may never be able to fully support any project since the research aims to perfect CBW, assuming that is the goal. It is possible that the lab might be developing countermeasures, disposal methods, non-lethal alternatives, or other projects that George might not find morally objectionable. In either case, he would have the PFD to be honest to his potential employer as to his willingness to engage in research to further CBW. This PFD also extends to himself, that he honestly assess and properly understand exactly what he finds objectionable, and what conditions would have to be met for him to work in that field. That self-knowledge is likely a PFD of self-improvement.
          To proceed, we'll need to make some assumptions about the scenario because it is necessary to know the nation's stance on CBW before one can possibly make a determination. If George were considering working for a State that actively supported the use of CBW, then, excluding some extreme circumstance, he would have a heavily weighted PFD of nonmaleficence to refuse the job; alternatively, based on a PFD of beneficence, he would have an option for a supererogatory action of taking the job to sabotage the State's efforts. While there are many historical examples of individuals that have done similar deeds, and were considered heroes for their efforts,15 there are just as many that have been executed as traitors and terrorists. I don't believe sabotage could ever be considered an ATCD, simply because it is arguably impossible to have a rational duty that requires that degree of personal sacrifice, a complete overriding or even disregard for all other current and future PFDs.16
          Assuming that George is capable of and seeking employment in the United States or US-like hypothetical country, we can conclude that any research that George would be doing would either be under the Biodefense program or the continuing program to destroy chemical agents. That is because of the ratification of all relevant treaties since 1997, and the continuing operations to destroy all CBW agents in the US arsenal, although this claim is not without controversy, as there are continual conflicting reports of US CBW research activities.17 Past attitudes and treaties do not guarantee future actions and all technological and scientific research have the potential to be weaponized, or otherwise abused. Still, stopping all research out of a PFD of nonmaleficence would arguably do more harm than good, provided that researchers in all fields remain ethically engaged. In either case, the only way George could truly know the character of the work is to be employed, which may generate new PFDs as he becomes familiar with the realities of the job. His PFD to fidelity (admitting to a future employer that he is morally against CBW) might work against him becoming employed, or it might work for him. Either way, how his interviewer will respond to his moral objections is beyond his control, but that does not excuse him from the PFD to report his misgivings.
          If the work is to generate new CBW agents, then he has a PFD of nonmaleficence, as clearly as if he were manufacturing bombs or bullets. Beyond that, the high probability of non-conventional retaliation of any use of a weapon of mass destruction is so high (America's Guaranteed Second-Strike policy) that aiding in the development of new weapons is contrary to the welfare of oneself and one's family. If the work is in Biodefense, there may be a PFD of beneficence, because it protects people from CBW attacks. Either way, an outsider is not likely to learn the truth, and government actions are not the only considerations.
          Seeking work that improves his family's lot is supported by the PFD of beneficence, and may carry a special weight given the cultural requirements of tending to your own family's needs. However, the PFD of fidelity requires that he isolate the desire to work from stereotypical heteronormative/sexist behavior patterns that may prejudice him against the current situation. If both he and his wife are equally capable parents and income-providers, this disposition must be explained. The situation seems to indicate that he is a less-capable parent, but four PFDs might override that consideration: fidelity, beneficence, justice, and self-improvement.
          The general duty to the truth requires that he confirm why he is considering employment in a field he finds morally wrong. The PFD of beneficence applies to his wife and children although in different ways. To his wife he has the duties to benefit/support her if she wishes to seek her own career, and to materially support her if they agree she should stay home with the children. These overlap with the PFD of justice, and perhaps a general PFD of reparation, as gender roles have been a serious challenge to equality for some time.
          To his children he owes the PFD of beneficence to provide for their needs and development, but this duty is shared equally with his wife. While he has the PFD of self-improvement, it is not possible to know what experiences will improve ourselves the most until after the fact. His time as a stay-at-home dad may be the best opportunity for self-improvement that he will ever have, but it is not likely to improve his career. In the scenario it seems that he has resolved these as he is seeking work, but since this course has led him to consider becoming complicit in killing people, he should reconsider everything that led him here.
          Clearly, there is far more to be said about this case. One could also examine the PFDs George has to, and because of the influential chemist, or expand the survey of PFDs to better capture all his duties, but space here is limited. If George's government is seeking weapons, his PFD of nonmaleficence should override other considerations because the likely consequences of CBW are extreme. However, if he lives in the modern world, were a majority of nation-states have banned CBW, then research projects he is likely to encounter will be in line with his general PFDs of nonmaleficence and beneficence. All relevant PFDs to his family are also supported. By my reading of the situation, he has the ATCD to pursue the job with both eyes wide open. Accepting the job requires that he stay ethically engaged, or risk becoming complicit.

Bibliography
Collina, Tom. 2013. “Chemical and Biological Weapons Status at a Glance.” Arms Control Today armscontrol.org. Washington D.C.: The Arms Control Association.

Timmons, Mark. 2013. Moral Theory: An Introduction. Kindle Edition. Plymouth: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.


1 Timmons 2013, 244.
2 Timmons 2013, 246.
3 Timmons 2013, 246.
4 Timmons 2013, 247-248.
5 Timmons 2013, 253.
6 Timmons 2013, 249-250.
7 Timmons 2013, 250.
8 Timmons 2013, 251.
9 Timmons 2013, 252.
10 Timmons 2013, 252.
11 Timmons 2013, 253.
12 Timmons 2013, 253.
13 Timmons 2013, 254.
14 Assignment prompt.
15 Here, I think of people like Oskar Schindler and Chiune Sugihara saving Jews during WWII, and Charles Hippolyte Labussiére destroying court records necessary for executions during the French Revolution. Many other names could be placed on this list.
16 The full set of all current and future PFDs that will be failed then entail further PFDs of reparations, which are also failed. An ATCD that requires death or comparably long prison sentence seems to me to lead to an infinite regress of failed duties. It is therefore unintelligible to say that ATCD could be rational. It might balance against all other current and future PFDs and allow for preference under discretion to decide the case, but even that cannot be fully rational.
17 Collina, 2013. “Chemical and Biological Weapons Status at a Glance”.

No comments:

Post a Comment